A mapping from a set $S$ to a set $T$
is a relationship
(rule, correspondence) that assigns to each
element of $S$ a uniquely determined element
of $T.$ The set $S$ is called the
domain
of the mapping, and the set $T$ is called the
codomain.
Mappings will generally be denoted by
Greek letters.
To indicate that $\alpha$ is a mapping from $S$
to $T,$ we shall write $\alpha:S\rightarrow T$ or
$S\stackrel{\alpha}\rightarrow T.$
If $x$ is an element of $S$, then $\alpha(x)$
will denote the unique element of $T$ that is assigned
to $x;$ the element $\alpha(x)$ is called
the image of $x$ under the mapping $\alpha.$
Sometimes, there will be a formula for $\alpha(x),$
as in the examples $f(x)=x^2$ and $f(x)=\sin x,$
but that certainly need not be the case.
Let $S=\{x,y,z\},$
$T=\{1,2,3\},$
$\alpha:S\rightarrow T$
defined by
$\alpha(x)=2,$
$\alpha(y)=1,$
$\alpha(z)=3,$
and
$\beta:S\rightarrow T$
defined by
$\beta(x)=1,$
$\beta(y)=3,$
$\beta(z)=1.$
In general, any two $\alpha$ and $\beta$
are said to be
equal mappings
if their domains are equal, their codomains
are equal, and $\alpha(x)=\beta(x)$ for every $x$
in their common domain.
In
,
$\alpha\ne\beta$
because, for instance,
$\alpha(y)=1\ne\beta(y)=3.$
There are 27 different mappings from $S$ to $T$
in .
There are $\abs{T}^{\abs{S}}$ mappings
$\alpha:S\rightarrow T.$
If $S$ is any set, we shall use $\iota$ (iota)
to denote the
identity mapping
from $S$ to $S,$ which is defined by
$\iota(x)=x$ for each $x\in S.$
If it is necessary to indicate which set $S$
is being considered, $\iota_s$ can be written
instead of $\iota.$
It is sometimes convenient to write
$x\stackrel{\alpha}\rightarrow y$
or $x\mapsto y$
to indicate that $y$ is the image of $x$ under a
mapping.
We may write $x\stackrel{\alpha}{\rightarrow} y,$
$x\mapsto y$ or $\alpha:x\mapsto y$ to indicate
$y$ is the image of $x$ under a mapping.
A mapping from the set of
ordered pairs
of real numbers to a real number, such
as addition
$(s,t)\rightarrow s+t,$
is an example of
an
operation on a set.
Unlike addition, subtraction
does not map $(s,t)$ and $(t,s)$
to the same element in $\R,$
illustrating the need for
the distinction implied by ordered
pairs, that $(s,t)\ne(t,s)$
when $s\ne t.$
If $\alpha:S\rightarrow T$ and $A$ is a subset of $S,$
then $\alpha(A)$ will denote the set of elements of $T$
that are images of elements of $A$ under the mapping
$\alpha$ and we may write
\(
\alpha(A)=\{\alpha(x):x\in A\}.
\)
The set $\alpha(A)$ is called
the image of $A$ under the mapping $\alpha.$
In ,
$\alpha(\{x,z\})=\{2,3\}$
and
$\beta(\{x,z\})=\{1\}.$
If $\alpha:S\rightarrow T$
then $\alpha(S)$ will be called
the image of $\alpha.$
If $\alpha:S\rightarrow T$
and $\alpha(S)=T,$
then $\alpha$ is said to be
onto
or a
surjection.
Thus, $\alpha$ is onto if
for each $y\in T$ there is
an $x\in S$ such that
$\alpha(x)=y.$
Stated another way,
$\alpha$ is onto if
$\alpha(S)=T,$ and
not onto if
$\alpha(S)\ne T.$
In terms of diagrams like those in
a mapping is onto provided
each element of the codomain has at least
one arrow pointing to it.
Thus, in
,
$\alpha$ is onto but
$\beta$ is not.
Neither
$f:\R\rightarrow\R$
nor $g:\R\rightarrow\R$
defined by
$f(x)=x^2$
and
$g(x)=\sin x$
are onto, since the image
of $f$ is the set of
non-negative real numbers
and the image of $g$
the set of real numbers
between
$-1$ and $1,$
inclusive.
A mapping $\alpha:S\rightarrow T$
is
one-to-one
if
$x\ne y$ implies $\alpha(x)\ne\alpha(y)$
for each $x,y\in S,$
or equivalently,
if
$\alpha(x)=\alpha(y)$
implies
$x=y.$
In terms of diagrams like those in
,
a mapping is one-to-one
provided no two arrows point to the same
element. Thus, in
,
$\alpha$ is one-to-one
but $\beta$ is not.
Neither $f$ nor $g$ in
,
are one-to-one since
$f(x)=x^2=f(-x)$
when $x\ne -x,$
and
$g(x)=\sin x=g(x+2n\pi)$
for all $x\in\R$
and integer $n$.
Let $\alpha:\N\rightarrow\N,$
$\beta:\N\rightarrow\N,$
$\alpha(n)=2n$
and
\[
\beta(n)=
\left\{
\begin{array}{cl}
(n+1)/2 &\text{if } n \text{ is odd}\\
n/2 &\text{if } n \text{ is even}
\end{array}
\right.
\]
Then $\alpha$ is one-to-one but not onto
and $\beta$ is onto but not one-to-one.
The existence of such mappings
is precisely what distinguishes
finite
from
infinite
sets.
A set $S$ is
infinite
if a mapping exists
from $S$ to $S$
that is one-to-one
but not onto.
The following notation is adopted.
-
$\N$ the set of all natural numbers, $\{1,2,3,\ldots\}$
-
$\Z$ the set of all integers $\{\ldots,-2,-1,0,1,2,\ldots\}$
-
$\Q$ the set of all rational numbers. That is, real numbers
of the form
$a/b$
where
$a,b\in\Z$
and
$b\ne0.$
-
$\R$ the set of all real numbers
-
$\C$ the set of all complex numbers
An
injection
is a one-to-one mapping.
A
surjection
is an onto mapping.
A
bijection
is a mapping that is both
one-to-one and onto, also
called a
one-to-one correspondence.
The
range
of a mapping often refers
to the codomain of a mapping,
but is also used by some authors
to refer to the image
of a mapping.