Chapter 1: The Real and Complex Number Systems
Highlights of Chapter 1
- 1.1 Rational numbers. $Q$ is incomplete. $p^2=2$ for $p\in Q$ has no solution
- 1.5 Ordered Set. Rudin calls a strict total order an order on S
- 1.7 Bounds
- 1.8 Least Upper Bound (infimum). Greatest Lower Bound (supremum). Definitions.
- 1.10 The Least Upper Bound Property
- 1.10 Equivalence of LUB/GLB Properties
- 1.12 Field definition and axioms
- 1.13 Notation and $Q$ is a field
- 1.14-16 Familiar results for fields
- 1.17 Ordered Fields
- 1.18 Familiar results for ordered fields
- 1.19 The Real Field, Existence Theorem. Proof in Chapter 1's Appendix
- 1.20 Archimedean Property of Real Numbers
- 1.20 Density of $Q$ in $R$
- 1.21 Reals are complete, $y^n=x$ for $x\in R^+$ and $n\in J$ has a unique solution.
- 1.22 Decimals
- 1.23 Extended Reals
- 1.24-34 Complex Number Field
- 1.35 Schwarz Inequality
- 1.36 Euclidean Vector Space. The Real Line. The Complex Plane. Euclidean space is also a Metric Space.
- APPENDIX. Proof of 1.19 Existence Theorem, due to Dedekind and Cantor.
Introduction
Proof. Suppose such $p$ exists. Then there are integers $m$ and $n$ such that $p = m/n,$ $n\neq 0$ and either $2 \nmid m$ or $2 \nmid n,$ and by \eqref{eq_sqrt2} \begin{equation} {m^2} = 2 {n^2} \end{equation} Thus, $2 \mid m^2$ so $2 \mid m.$ (If $m$ were odd $m^2$ would be.) So $4 \mid m^2$ so $4 \mid 2 {n^2}$ so $2 \mid n^2$ so $2 \mid n,$ a contradiction.
Let $q$ be defined in terms of $p>0$ as follows: \begin{equation} \label{rud_q_from_p} q = p - \frac{p^2 - 2}{p + 2} = \frac{2p + 2}{p + 2} \end{equation} Then \begin{equation} \label{rud_sq_q_from_p} q^2 - 2 = \frac{2(p^2 - 2)}{(p+2)^2} \end{equation}
If $p\in A$ then $p^2-2\lt0,$
\eqref{rud_q_from_p} shows that
$q\gt p,$
and \eqref{rud_sq_q_from_p}
shows that $q^2\lt2.$ Thus,
$q\in A$ .
If $p\in B$ then $p^2-2\gt0,$ \eqref{rud_q_from_p} shows that $0\lt q\lt p$ and \eqref{rud_sq_q_from_p} shows that $q^2\gt2.$ Thus, $q\in B.$
Ordered Sets
-
Trichotomy. If $x\in S$ and $y\in S,$ then exactly one of the following is true: $x\lt y,$ $x=y,$ $x\gt y.$ -
Transitivity. If $x,y,z\in S$ and $x\lt y$ and $y\lt z$ then $x < z.$
- $\alpha$ is an upper bound of $E.$
- if $\gamma\lt\alpha$ then $\gamma$ is not an upper bound of $E.$
- Consider the sets from Rudin 1.1 $A = \{ p \in Q : p^2 < 2 \}$ and $B = \{ p \in Q : p^2 > 2 \}.$ $A$ has no least upper bound in $Q$ and $B$ has no greatest lower bound in $Q.$
- If $\alpha \in \sup{E}$ exists, then $\alpha$ may or may not be a member of $E.$
Proof.
Since $E$ is bounded below, the
set of all lower bounds (in $S$) of
$E$ is nonempty. Denote this nonempty
subset of $S$ by $L.$ We first show
that $L$ has the least upper bound.
Since $L$ is the set of all lower
bounds of $E,$ that means
$\forall x\in L:x\leq y$;
but this equivalently means that
$E$ is the set of all upper bounds
of $L.$
Since $E$ is nonempty it follows
that $L$ is bounded above, i.e.
$\exists y\in E:\forall x\in L: y\geq x.$
We have shown that $L$ is a nonempty
subset of $S$ and $L$ is bounded
above.
Since $S$ has the least upper bound
property, it follows that $L$ has the
least upper bound in $S.$ Denote it
by $\alpha=\sup{L}.$ If
$\gamma\lt\alpha,$ then $\gamma$ is not
an upper bound of $L,$ since
$\alpha=\sup{L}.$
So $\gamma\notin E.$
Thus, $\forall x\in E:\alpha\leq x,$
so $\alpha$ is a lower bound of $E,$
Fields
-
Axioms for Addition
-
Closure. $F$ is closed under Addition.
\( (\forall x,y\in F) (x+y\in F). \) -
Commutative. Addition is commutative in $F.$
\( (\forall x,y\in F) (x+y=y+x). \) -
Associative. Addition is associative in $F.$
\( (\forall x,y,z\in F) [(x+y)+z=x+(y+z)]. \) -
Additive Identity
\( (\exists 0\in F) (\forall x \in F) (0+x=x). \) -
Additive Inverse
\( (\forall x\in F) (\exists (-x)\in F) (x+(-x)=0). \)
-
-
Axioms for Multiplication
-
Closure. $F$ is closed under Multiplication.
\( (\forall x,y\in F) (xy \in F) \) -
Commutative. ) Multiplication is commutative in $F.$
\( (\forall x,y\in F) (xy=yx). \) -
Associative. Multiplication is associative in $F.$
\( (\forall x,y,z\in F) [(xy)z=x(yz)]. \) -
Multiplicative Identity.
\( (\exists 1 \in F) (\forall x \in F) (1x=x). \) -
Multiplicative Inverse
\( (\forall x\in F) (\exists (1/x)\in F) (x(1/x)=1). \)
-
-
The Distributive Law
-
Distributive. Multiplication is distributive over addition in $F.$
\( (\forall x,y,z\in F) [x(y+z)=xy+xz)] \)
-
The Real Field
Proof. Since $x\lt y$ we have $y-x\gt 0$ and the Archimedean property furnishes a positive integer $n$ such that \[ n(y-x)\gt 1. \] Apply Archimedes again to obtain positive integers $m_1$ and $m_2$ such that $m_1\gt nx$ and $m_2\gt -nx.$ Then \[ -m_2\lt nx \lt m_1. \] Hence there is an integer $m$ (with $-m_2\le m\le m_1$) such that \[ m-1\le nx \lt m. \] If we combine these inequalities we obtain \[ nx\lt m\le 1+nx\lt ny. \] Since $n\gt 0,$ it follows that \[ x\lt m/n\lt y. \] This proves the theorem with $p=m/n.$
The Extended Real Number System
The Complex Field
Euclidean Spaces
Guevara Supplement for Chapter 1
Proof. Suppose not and let $\alpha\in S.$ Then \( \neg\forall x (x\in\varnothing\Rightarrow x\leq\alpha), \) (Rudin 1.7), so \( \exists x (x\in\varnothing\wedge x\gt\alpha), \) a contradiction. Bounded below proceeds similarly.
Proof. Let $\alpha$ denote the least element of $S.$ Then $\alpha=\inf{S}.$ So $\forall x\in S:\alpha\lt x,$ and $\alpha$ is an upper bound of $\varnothing$ (Guevara 1.3). Suppose $\gamma\lt\alpha$ and that $\gamma$ is an upper bound of $\varnothing.$ Then $\gamma\in S$ so $\alpha\le\gamma,$ contradiction. Therefore, if $\gamma\lt\alpha$ then $\gamma$ is not an upper bound of $\varnothing.$
Proof. TBD
Proof. Suppose the contrary. Then for some $x,$ $x\in(m,n)$ and $x\not\in[k-1,k)$ for any $k\in[m,n].$ Thus, $x\not\in\bigcup_{k\in[m,n]}[k-1,k)$ $=[m-1,n).$ Thus, $x\not\in(m,n)\subseteq[m-1,n),$ a contradiction.